This is the old version of the H2O platform and is now read-only. This means you can view content but cannot create content. You can access the new platform at https://opencasebook.org. Thank you.
Edit playlist item notes below to have a mix of public & private notes, or:
MAKE ALL NOTES PUBLIC (0/2 playlist item notes are public) MAKE ALL NOTES PRIVATE (2/2 playlist item notes are private)1 | Show/Hide More | IV.A. Justification |
1.1 | Show/Hide More | IV.A.i. Self-Defense |
In the next few sections, we will explore situations in which the commission of what might otherwise be a crime does not result in punishment. Broadly speaking, the doctrines in this area of criminal law are grouped into “justification” and “excuse.” In this section, we will discuss the first kind of justification: self-defense.
Self-defense justifies a crime—more than excusing it, it affirms that what would otherwise be a criminal act is in fact desirable in a given situation. In cases of legal self-defense, our system treats a person who kills or injures as morally right, even when they kill intentionally.
Legalizing assault, killing, or other forceful actions inevitably devolves the state’s usual monopoly on the legitimate use of force, to individual persons capable of abusing it. Thus, legal self-defense raises several concerns. Should self-defense be a last resort? Must the defender respond with minimal force, or is any amount of force legitimate? Must the threat be actual, subjective, or objectively reasonable?
Different jurisdictions have created different systems. Compare the questions raised by situations such as ongoing abusive domestic relationships or an encounter with a stranger on the subway. As you read the following cases, consider the criminal system’s difficulty in managing individuals’ legal use of force, and notice how the law attempts to channel and contain that Pandora’s box.
1.1.1 | Show/Hide More | People v. Goetz |
1.1.3 | Show/Hide More | State v. Kelly |
1.1.4 | Show/Hide More | State v. Norman |
1.1.5 | Show/Hide More | Fisher v. State |
1.1.6 | Show/Hide More | United States v. Urena |
1.1.7 | Show/Hide More | State v. Abbott |
1.1.8 | Show/Hide More | Jeannie Suk, At Home in the Law, Chapter 3 - Scenes of Self-Defense |
1.2 | Show/Hide More | IV.B.ii. Necessity |
Necessity may also justify action that would otherwise be criminal. The category is significantly narrower than self-defense, and claims of necessity are rarely successful. Necessity requires imminent and grave harm that results through no fault of the defendant. The defendant must take forceful action only when the benefits clearly outweigh the harms.
As you will see, the cases in this section often deal with significantly more extreme fact patterns than the self-defense cases. Why is the necessity justification narrowly construed?
1.2.1 | Show/Hide More | Regina v. Dudley and Stephens |
1.2.2 | Show/Hide More | Cleveland v. Anchorage |
1.2.3 | Show/Hide More | People v. Unger |
1.2.5 | Show/Hide More | PCAT v. State of Israel |
2 | Show/Hide More | IV.B. Excuse |
2.1 | Show/Hide More | IV.B.i. Duress |
2.1.2 | Show/Hide More | Banyard v. State |
2.1.3 | Show/Hide More | United States v. Fleming |
2.1.4 | Show/Hide More | United States v. Chi Tong Kuok |
2.2 | Show/Hide More | IV.B.ii. Insanity |
The insanity excuse has been around for a long time, even as society’s social and scientific understandings of insanity have evolved. As an excuse, rather than a justification, insanity doctrine does not hold that the criminal act was morally correct, but rather that the insane person is not responsible for a morally wrong action.
The cases and readings in this section introduce some of the formulations of the insanity defense that are currently in use. Consider how the various formulations balance the moral and the medical. According to one insanity rule, the ability to tell right from wrong is central to the insanity inquiry. According to another, self-control is key, as an irresistible impulse may excuse culpability. The Model Penal Code applies a sort of hybrid. Each major test is followed in a variety of jurisdictions, and some jurisdictions follow yet another test or provide for no insanity defense at all. What does the sheer diversity of approaches and standards tell us about the insanity excuse? Should the very diversity of approaches implicate fairness concerns?
Consider why our criminal justice system may not seek to punish the insane. How does insanity implicate the traditional justifications of punishment (retribution, deterrence, incapacitation, and rehabilitation)? Since criminal punishment undoubtedly has a moral component, what should be the role of science in defining who is insane and who is excused due to insanity? Are those the same questions, or are they different?
Lastly, insanity may implicate more than the question of excuse. Even if someone is guilty, they may be “guilty but mentally ill.” Consider what role insanity or mental illness may play in establishing the other elements of a crime, such as mens rea.
2.2.1 | Show/Hide More | Galloway v. State |
2.2.2 | Show/Hide More | The King v. Porter |
2.2.3 | Show/Hide More | M'Naghten's Case |
2.2.4 | Show/Hide More | State v. Singleton |
2.2.5 | Show/Hide More | Blake v. United States |
2.2.7 | Show/Hide More | United States v. Lyons |
2.2.8 | Show/Hide More | Commonwealth v. DiPadova |
2.3 | Show/Hide More | IV.B.iii. Diminished Capacity |
2.3.1 | Show/Hide More | United States v. Brawner |
2.4 | Show/Hide More | IV.B.iv. Environmental Deprivation |
2.4.1 | Show/Hide More | Richard Delgado — 'Rotten Social Background': Should the Criminal Law Recognize a Defense of Severe Environmental Deprivation? |
May 27, 2016
Griswold Reading Groups
Harvard Law School
Find Items |
Search below to find items, then drag and drop items onto playlists you own. To add items to nested playlists, you must first expand those playlists.
This is the old version of the H2O platform and is now read-only. This means you can view content but cannot create content. If you would like access to the new version of the H2O platform and have not already been contacted by a member of our team, please contact us at h2o@cyber.law.harvard.edu. Thank you.